Notes on the Prehistory of Camouflage and Mimicry as Cultural Techniques

This article appears in West 86th Vol. 30 No. 1 / Spring–Summer 2023

The relations between human and animal camouflage have rarely been investigated. Current scholarship, focusing on the evolutionary and military aspects of camouflage, has overshadowed earlier thinking about camouflage and mimicry as shared animal and human features. Reconstructing some of the main elements of those early views, this article argues that, in humans, camouflage should be considered as a cultural technique. Three stages in the “prehistory” of camouflage, which are also three varieties of cultural contexts, are discussed: the hunt, in which camouflage behavior is shared by animals and humans; camouflage behavior among humans, analyzed in terms of simulation and conceived or figured in terms of animal behavior; and camouflage seen as the manifestation of emerging human material culture.

Camouflage and mimicry are not the domain of animals alone. Humans also engage in these image-making practices, in hunting, war, fashion, social behavior, and the arts. Consider, for instance, an Anglo-Saxon ornament from Sutton Hoo in which animal figures are hidden in a trellis of metal straps (fig. 1). Hunters use camouflage, covering themselves in foliage, as in this fifteenth-century manuscript illumination (fig. 2), or disguising themselves as white wolves in George Catlin’s North American Indian Portfolio (fig. 3). In the arts, camouflage sometimes takes the shape of zoomorphism: this base of a Roman altar from the second century CE looks like a lion partly disguised as a trapezoidal piece of sculpture (fig. 4). Camouflage is also present in many other varieties of disguising, hiding, and covering to be found in the decorative arts and fashion. See, for instance, the practice of hiding brickwork behind oak paneling, which in this example is made to look like linen folds (fig. 5). Among humans, camouflage also occurs in social behavior, as when people disguise their social status, desires, or motives behind appearances they judge to be more acceptable or effective. The novels of writers such as Thomas Mann, Marcel Proust, and Honoré de Balzac are full of social camouflage.

Fig. 1. Sutton Hoo belt buckle, early 7th century CE. Gold and niello, 2¼ × 5¼ in. (5.6 × 13.2 cm). The British Museum, London (1939,1010.1). © Trustees of the British Museum.

 

Fig. 2. Anonymous illustration showing camouflaged hunters preparing to attack a deer, ca. 1430–40. Tempera colors, gold paint, silver paint, and gold leaf on parchment, 10⅜ × 7¼ in. (26.4 × 18.4 cm). From Gaston Phébus, Livre de Chasse, MS 27, fol. 101, J. Paul Getty Museum, Los Angeles (87.MR.34.109).

 

Fig. 3. George Catlin (American, 1796–1872), Buffalo Hunt under the Wolf-Skin Mask, 1832–33. Oil on canvas, 24 × 29 in. (60.9 × 73.7 cm). Smithsonian American Art Museum, Washington, DC, gift of Mrs. Joseph Harrison Jr. (1985.66.414).

 

Altar base commonly known as the Borghese Altar, Roman, first half of the second century CE. Marble, 70⅞ × 56 in. (180 × 142 cm). Musée du Louvre, Paris (MA 672). Photo: Caroline van Eck.

 

Fig. 5. Oak linenfold paneling, ca. 1830. Dining Hall, King’s College, Cambridge, England. Photo: Caroline van Eck.

These examples of what might provisionally be called the shared domain of animal and human camouflage and mimicry raise many questions about the psychological, evolutionary, and behavioral relations between animals and humans. For art historians, visual similarities between animal and human camouflage are baffling, as are most cases of image-making that transcend the human/animal divide. One of the few exceptions is the painting animal, particularly in depictions of monkeys as painters.1vVisual similarities between human artifacts and animal camouflage, such as those between the Roman altar (see fig. 4) and the hermit crab shown in figure 6, could be considered instances of pseudomorphism, which Erwin Panofsky defined as “the emergence of a form A, morphologically analogous to, or even identical with, a form B, yet entirely unrelated to it from a genetic point of view.” Invoking pseudomorphism is the art historian’s way of noting enigmatic formal similarities while dismissing them as fortuitous because there is no evidence of a historical connection between the forms nor is there any convincing conceptual link.2

Fig. 6. Hermit crab. Photograph by P. Popper. From Roger Caillois, Le Mimétisme Animal (Paris: Hachette, 1961), fig. 58.

On the other hand, giving an exclusively evolutionary account of the relation between animal and human camouflage is also problematic. Biological evolution is much slower than cultural developments; animal camouflage is genetically determined and shaped by instinct and successful adaptation, whereas human camouflage is taught, conscious, and often intentional. Therefore, there is no direct, causal relation between the two. Also, the fact that camouflage was first theorized in the context of the evolution theory developed by Charles Darwin and Alfred Russel Wallace does not imply that evolution offers a complete explanation of human camouflage. Ultimately, the fact that humans engage in camouflage and mimicry does not require an evolutionary explanation. Humans are animals and therefore share survival and other skills with animals, but seeking an evolutionary antecedent or cause for human varieties of camouflage might be described as a misguided exercise in skeuomorphism. In design studies this term refers to the use of existing forms for new inventions, in the way that the first printed books were designed to look like manuscripts, or a Mac hard disk to resemble an eighteenth-century Japanese lacquer writing box. When applied to camouflage, it would suggest that human camouflage is a spurious throwback to older, animal behavior.

To clarify the relation between animal and human camouflage, I want to reconstruct some main points of the archaeology or prehistory of thinking about camouflage and mimicry as shared animal and human features and present aspects of the cultural contexts in which such thinking took place: the hunt, dissimulation at court, and the arts considered as masquerade. This prehistory, largely obscured by the focus in current scholarship on the evolutionary and military aspects of camouflage, will significantly extend the range of examples and ideas that existed about these same topics prior to their present codifications.3 It will also show that military and evolutionary conceptions of camouflage have obscured its much wider role, which goes beyond protective adaptation and should be considered as a cultural technique in humans. Three stages will be examined in this prehistory—stages that are also varieties of cultural contexts. In the first, camouflage behavior is discussed as a common feature shared by animals and humans in the hunt, where both can be hunter as well as prey; in the second, camouflage among humans is discussed in terms of simulation and conceived, or figured, in terms of animal behavior; and in the third, camouflage is seen as the manifestation of emerging human material culture.

This last stage provides a direct link to considering human camouflage as a cultural technique. This I define, following Thomas Macho, as a symbolic technique that cannot be produced without a medium and at the same time cannot be reduced to it; that allows for self-referentiality or thematization; and that is older than its conceptualization. The cultural techniques of writing, singing, and weaving, for instance, existed before they were codified in writing and, unlike ploughing or fishing, can be thematized: one can sing about singing or weave a tapestry that depicts weaving, but one cannot represent fishing in an act of fishing. Another important aspect signaled by Macho is that cultural techniques are often techniques of the self: they serve to present or construct a certain identity.4  To Macho’s definition I would add that cultural techniques often emerge on the cusp of the transition from instinctual, innate behavior to cultural and learned activities and the production of artifacts. Thinking about human camouflage in these terms will help to address the problems raised by evolutionary explanations of its development. Evolution theory has made the study of this subject particularly complex because of the clash between the longue durée of evolutionary development in nature and the short time span of cultural developments and because of the lack of fit between the low resolution of evolutionary analysis— considering developments of species over long periods—and the close scrutiny, in culture studies, of individual cases over short periods. 5

1.  Camouflage and mimicry: some preliminary definitions

The term camouflage is a recent one, first attested in 1887 in French and subsequently in English.6  It is derived from the noun camouflet, first documented in 1611 in the sense of smoke blown into somebody’s eyes.7 Whereas biologists generally use the term camouflage to refer to the protective characteristics an animal takes on to blend with its inanimate surroundings, mimicry refers to an animal’s adoption of the behavior and appearance of another animal.8 According to the Oxford English Dictionary, the word mimicry, defined as “the art of depicting character by mimetic gestures,” was first attested in 1637 and derives from the Greek ethologia, the understanding of character as displayed in behavior. The term was first used in entomology in 1815 in William Kirby and William Spence’s An Introduction to Entomology. 9  In a discussion of what would now be called camouflage, the authors cite the case of Leptocerus atratus, a kind of mayfly that resembled its habitat so closely that they were often unable to distinguish the insect from the plant it frequented. “The birds,” they wrote, “probably often make the same mistake and pass it by.” 10 At present, mimicry is generally understood to encompass crypsis, the use of strategies to prevent detection, and masquerade, which aims at avoiding recognition by the predator. 11

Camouflage became a central issue in the life sciences as a result of the discoveries by Bates, Wallace, and Darwin, in the 1850s, of adaptive behavior as a means of survival.12 In biology, camouflage quickly became a central testing ground for evolution theory because it enabled investigators to observe in nature how the adaptation of species to their environment evolved and how exactly the fittest survived. Henry Walter Bates’s study of mimicry among butterflies, first published in 1862, was one of the first independent fieldwork confirmations of Darwin’s theories.13 Bates showed, for instance, that the Leptalis butterfly, of the Pieridae family, mimics another genus, Ithomia, from the Heliconidae family. Predator birds find the Ithomia revolting to eat, whereas the Leptalis are quite tasty to them. Connecting mimicry to survival by adaptation, Bates showed that the survival of the Leptalis butterflies is based on their quite large numbers; since there is heavy selection and constant evolution of new species, the species that looks more like the Ithomia is more likely to survive.14

Wallace spent much of his life studying camouflage and mimicry behavior among insects in Amazonia, coming very close to being the discoverer of evolution theory. In “Mimicry and Other Protective Resemblances among Animals,” a long essay published in 1867 in which he reviewed various studies of camouflage and mimicry, Wallace set out the state-of-the-art view of camouflage, its role in the adaptation and survival of species, and the problems still unsolved. He cites some wonderful examples, such as the Kallima butterfly of India and Malaysia, whose protective resemblance to its environment is so sophisticated that its wings do not just resemble the leaves, bark, and shrubs of its habitat but also display “powdery black dots” that resemble the fungi on the leaves, thus representing, as Wallace puts it, “leaves in every state of decay” (fig. 7). 15

Fig. 7. Kallima inachus butterfly. Black spots on the wings resemble fungi that grow on plants in the butterfly’s habitat. Photo: Wikimedia Commons.

Such protective resemblance consists not only of a repertory of forms, shapes, sizes, textures, and colors of skin surfaces but also of behaviors and habits. Together these traits produce disguises that are almost perfect, given the large number of insects that possess them. Wallace also notes that such resemblances do not involve conscious, intentional imitation, but rather a patterning and shaping of external appearance that occur in particular among animals that multiply rapidly, with incessant slight variations resulting in successful adaptation and hence survival. The disputed role of intentionality in such resemblances would become a recurring issue among evolutionary biologists, leading to intense debate in Cambridge in the 1930s and ’40s. As Hugh Cott, one of the pioneering students of animal mimicry and particularly of adaptive coloring and patterning in birds, wrote: “An analogy must not be carried too far. The present one stops short at the point where we realize that while man-made contrivances have been invented, natural adaptations have evolved…. Nevertheless both are intimately related to the pressing needs for survival in this transitory life.”16

At the same time, Wallace introduced a gradual shift of focus from camouflage as a feature of the external appearance of animals to camouflage as a variety of behavior: animals often do not look like their habitat but, while remaining quite conspicuous, start to behave like other animals that are less attractive to their predators: “They appear like actors or masqueraders dressed up and painted for amusement, or like swindlers endeavouring to pass themselves off for well-known or respectable members of society.”17

Wallace makes another major point here, asserting that there is no radical division between animal and human capacities for creating camouflage and being fooled by it: “For it is evident that if colours which please us also attract them [animals], and if the various disguises which have been enumerated are equally deceptive to them as to ourselves, then both their powers of vision and their faculties of perception and emotion must be essentially of the same nature as our own—a fact of high philosophical importance in the study of our own nature and our own relation to the lower animals.”18

Camouflage posed two major problems from the moment it became a core part of evolution theory. The first was how to account for the enormous variety of protective adaptation on show in nature. This was a problem because, as the biologist Richard Swann Lull wrote in 1917: “We cannot conceive of selection taking an adaptation past the point of efficacy.”19The second problem was to explain how creatures produce offspring that are like themselves but different in subtle visual ways. This would be solved only in the 1960s and ’70s, when evolutionary biology and genomics met and a genetic account of the development and persistence of camouflage over successive generations of an animal species could be developed and tested.20

Accounts of camouflage and mimicry that concentrated exclusively on evolutionary function—on the adaptation of traits solely for purposes of survival—were also criticized by two men who were both artists and biologists: Roger Caillois and Vladimir Nabokov. As is well known, Nabokov came from a family of scientists and spent much of his life, when not writing, pursuing and studying butterflies. He became the curator of lepidoptera at Harvard’s Museum of Comparative Zoology, identified new species, and published major articles on their classification. He was also fascinated by camouflage and mimicry, lectured on the topic, and worked on a manuscript about it, which is now lost.21 Fortunately, mimicry figures large in Nabokov’s fiction, where he scattered tantalizing observations about the similarities between butterflies and plants, between animals and art, calling them “those rhymes of nature.”22 In The Gift (1933–38) he fires off a series of mimetic disguises that far elude evolutionary explanation:

[An] incredible artistic wit of mimetic disguise, which was not explainable by the struggle for existence (the rough haste of evolution’s unskilled forces), was too refined for the mere deceiving of accidental predators, feathered, scaled and otherwise (not very fastidious, but then not too fond of butterflies), and seemed to have been invented by some waggish artist precisely for the intelligent eyes of man…; [he spoke about] these magic masks of mimicry; about the enormous moth which in a state of repose assumes the image of a snake looking at you … and about the curious harem of that famous African swallow-tail, whose variously disguised females copy in color, shape and even flight half a dozen different species … which are also the models of numerous other mimics.23

These observations all point to the inescapable but inexplicable similarities between animal and human mimicry in behavior and art. Nabokov took a rather transcendental, Kant-inspired position on these similarities: camouflage exists only in the eye of the beholder, and judgments about camouflage are therefore closer to aesthetic judgments than to scientific theories about matters of fact or cause and effect. Also, he argued against Darwinist gradualist accounts of camouflage. For Nabokov, the infinite richness of camouflage could not be explained by the endless hit-or-miss and tinkering of survival by adaptation. Instead, he turned to theorists of morphogenesis such as the French philosopher Henri Bergson, the Russian Lev Berg, and Scottish biologist D’Arcy Thompson, author of On Growth and Form (1917), all of whom argued, in various ways, that the actual life of an organism may affect its development and phenotype, thus influencing its chance of being selected and thus surviving.24

This view raises fascinating issues about the epistemological status of judgments about camouflage and its evolution that cannot be pursued here, but I want to stress how clearly and compellingly Nabokov signals the similarities between natural and artistic camouflage and mimicry. At the same time he emphasized the problems of producing an economical theoretical and historical account of the actual evolution of camouflage and mimicry through the long periods of species development.

The poet and historian of biology Roger Caillois (1913–1978) provides a very different perspective. In his youth he was part of André Breton’s Surrealist circle. Caillois’s early, prewar writings on praying mantises and other picturesque insects can perhaps best be described as essays in the cultural history of biology. They question how certain animals, such as the praying mantis or the jellyfish (suggestively called méduse in French), can over the centuries acquire such rich incrustations of myth, beliefs, and psychoanalytic theories.25 In his prewar work Caillois connected camouflage in animals and humans to all kinds of psychopathology and even to the human desire to disappear into petrification and nothingness. His 1963 book on animal mimetism, Le mimétisme animal, far less known, is a much more sober affair. It is concerned with developing an understanding of camouflage that goes beyond evolutionary monocausalism. Caillois presents only one argument, but one that is difficult to ignore. Very often, camouflage does not work effectively in nature because, for instance, a predatory animal can still smell its prey despite the latter’s careful disguise as a piece of rock or a staring owl (fig. 8). The formal repertoire, and behavior, of camouflage is far too lavish, elaborate, varied, and luxuriant to serve the sole purpose of protective adaptation. As Caillois put it: “Camouflage is often useless…. There is a luxury of precaution, and an excess of simulacrum.”26

Fig. 8. Caligo prometheus butterfly. The insect’s wings open to reveal two circles that look like eyes, thought by some to deter predators. Photo: Wikimedia Commons.

Caillois subsumes camouflage and mimicry under the broad category of animal mimetism: the ability of animals to display appearances that imitate traits of other animals or their environment, often without conscious intention or comprehension. The formal similarities between animal mimetism and human image-making raise the question of whether there are any connections between the two. Caillois argues that there is a clear connection: what we would call its performative aspect:

The connection of mimetism and such circles [markings on the wings of the Caligo prometheus butterfly] cannot be due to chance. There is a link between the two phenomena that we have to discern. I perceive it in the display mechanism of these fascinating circles. It is not enough for them to exist, they have to appear. Initially invisible, they suddenly burst into view [when the butterfly opens its wings]. Camouflage merges [the insect] with its environment and prevents it from being seen. But then suddenly, where there seemed to be nothing, two enormous circles emerge, vivdly coloured, improbable, whose fixedness fascinates…. The insect operates in the manner of a fold-out mask: it substitutes one appearance for another, which frightens. Or better: instead of nothingness, there is suddenly the face of terror.27

Here Caillois reaches a position that is very close to Nabokov’s in its attention to the theatrical nature of camouflage, but as far as I know, Caillois was not aware of Nabokov’s work.28 In any case, neither writer’s reflections on camouflage were taken up by biologists at the time of their publication, and both remain controversial among historians of evolution theory.29

After genetic accounts of camouflage were developed, the topic returned to the center of the life sciences in the 1990s. The shift occurred primarily because research into the physical mechanisms that produce camouflage features in animals and the perception of camouflage by predators had taken off.30 Another contributing factor was the resumption of discussions on the respective roles of nature and culture in the development of human and nonhuman animals. These conversations picked up nearly a century after the failed attempts, about 1900, to map the development of the human species onto the adaptive behavior of individual animals and humans—that is, to map phylogeny onto ontogeny. Those earlier efforts had been particularly popular in Germany, where Nietzsche claimed that mimicry in humans is one of the constituents or crucial instruments of the Wille zur Macht (will to power).31 In an argument that announces many of the themes of present-day discussions about mimicry, he rejected the survival of the species as mimicry’s main driver, arguing instead that mimicry is the main realization of the will to power, especially in the weak, who must be deceitful to survive. Nietzsche added another consideration: that of the aesthetic luxuriance and variety of mimicry in nature. Pigments, he contended, are produced in nature to please and seduce. They exert yet another variety of power, since the resulting seduction robs its object of free will and attention and acts on its emotions. Thus, pleasure and attraction are the origins of both art and lies.

There is still another implication: for strategies of pleasing and seduction to succeed in protecting potential prey, the prey needs to understand the mind and desires of the predator. The primal situation of ornamental pigmentation, created for survival, seduction, and aesthetic pleasure, is therefore also the origin of empathy, of understanding other minds, and of psychology. This is stated clearly in Nietzsche’s Morgenröthe (1881), one of the most explicit and sustained projections of animal mimicry onto human behavior:

Animals and morality.—The practices demanded in polite society: careful avoidance of … the presumptuous, the suppression of one’s virtues as well as one’s strongest inclinations … all this is to be found as a social morality in a crude form everywhere, even in the depths of the animal world—and only at this depth do we see the purpose of all these amiable precautions: one wishes to elude one’s pursuers and be favoured in the pursuit of one’s prey. For that reason the animals learn to master themselves and alter their form, so that many, for example, adapt their colouring to the colouring of their surroundings … or assume the forms and colours of another animal or of sand, leaves, lichen, fungus (what English researchers designate [as] “mimicry”)…. All the subtle ways we have of appearing fortunate, grateful, powerful, enamoured have their easily discoverable parallels in the animal world.32

In the 1990s and 2000s the old nature/nurture debate concerning camouflage was revived because the impact of behavior on genetic modification had become increasingly apparent, as had the transmission of knowledge and skills over generations within a species. 33 Finally, the revival of animal ethology by Frans de Waal and other primate specialists showed again, from a different perspective, that camouflage and mimicry are not determined solely by the genetic pool but that such strategies are culturally constituted practices, among animals as among humans, that draw on empathy, as Nietzsche had argued.34

2. Camouflage and mimicry in human culture and behavior
2.1. Camouflage in hunting

Long before their codification in evolution theory, camouflage and mimicry were part of human culture. Among the oldest-surviving human artifacts are depictions of humans masquerading as animals: a cave painting from South Africa from ca. 30,000 BCE shows a huntsman wearing an animal mask and tail (fig. 9). During building works in Berlin in 1953, a giant mask made from the skull and antlers of a deer was found. Created between 8770 and 8750 BCE (fig. 10), the object belongs to a group of early Mesolithic antler masks or caps found in Germany as well as in Star Carr, near Scarborough, England. The careful cutting of the skull, the removal of half of the antlers, and the holes drilled through the skull so that it could be fastened to the wearer’s head show that this prey was adapted to become a mask.35The oldest-surviving written description of a masquerade in which humans take on the physical characteristics of an animal to avoid detection is probably Homer’s account of Odysseus’s escape from Polyphemus. The Greek hero’s subterfuge—he passes his comrades off as the blinded giant’s sheep—is depicted, for instance, in Jacob Jordaens’s painting of circa 1635, now in the Pushkin Museum, Moscow (fig. 11).36

Fig. 9. Cave painting depicting a human figure with animal head and tail and probably covered entirely with an animal skin, a common method of camouflage used by Bushmen during hunts. South Africa, ca. 30,000 BCE. Photo: Peabody Museum, Yale University/Artstor.

 

Fig. 10. Mask made from the skull and antlers of a deer, ca. 8770 BCE. Stadtmuseum Berlin (I/82/26). Photo: Wikimedia Commons.

 

Fig. 11. Jacob Jordaens (Flemish, 1593–1678), Odysseus in the Cave of Polyphemus, ca. 1635. Oil on canvas, 24 × 38¼ in. (61 × 97 cm). Pushkin State Museum of Fine Arts, Moscow. Photo: Wikimedia Commons.

The use of camouflage among animals and humans was well documented in antiquity. Aristotle described the octopus’s changes in color to adapt to changes in its environment, and Philostratus recorded pirates’ use of protective coloring for their ships.37 The treatise on fishing by Oppianus of Cyzicos, written about 180 CE, and the epic poem on hunting written by Oppianus of Apameia after 198 CE, discuss camouflage elements in the traps, nets, and other devices used to catch prey.38 As Marcel Detienne and Jean-Pierre Vernant have pointed out in their study of cunning in Greek culture, camouflage was employed by both animals and humans; both take on the role of the hunter and the hunted. Marine animals in particular were known to excel in the use of adaptive coloration: “By means of their technè octopuses disappear into the rock to which they attach themselves.”39 Dissimulation is practiced equally by the hunter and the hunted: “silent and invisible, hunters and fishermen alike must make themselves into prey.”40 The print cycle Venationes Ferarum, Avium, Piscium (Chasing Wild Animals, Birds and Fish), engraved by Philips Galle in 1578 and based on designs by Jan van der Straet (known as Stradanus) for the Medici Villa at Poggio a Caiano, shows the use of so-called Attrappe-Kuhen (catcher cows) that served as decoys for deer and protective covering for the hunters (fig. 12). Contemporary captions to two of these prints point to major elements in subsequent discussions of camouflage as a cultural technique: its fictional character and its being a kind of dress or costume. One of the captions states that hunters protected by fictional cows kill the frightened deer; the other explains that the huntsman proceeds dressed as a cow.41

Fig. 12. Phillips Galle (Netherlandish, 1537–1612), after a design by Johannes van der Straet, known as Stradanus (Netherlandish, 1523–1605), Deer Hunting with the Use of Camouflage, 1578. Engraving, 8⅛ × 11 in. (20.6 × 27.9 cm). Rijksmuseum, Amsterdam (RP-P-1891-A-16423).

Dissimulation as the wider cultural concept for understanding animal and human behavior returns in emblem books. Published in 1664, the emblem book of Jacobus Bornitius contains an image that had appeared twenty-seven years earlier, in Jacob Cats’s Proteus ofte Minnebeelden verandert in Sinnebeelden, of 1627. It shows a bird-catcher keeping an eye on his traps from behind the dappled patterns made by the leaves of the tree in which he’s hiding. The device carries this warning: “Look carefully whom you trust: such is the dissimulation of the world!/If somebody says something, he denies it: if he denies it, he says it of himself.”42

Dissimulation was often identified as a defining feature of civilized life in the early modern period: it is a frequent topic in manuals for courtiers, such as Castiglione’s; it was captured in the title of Torquato Accetto’s treatise on honest dissimulation; and it is often connected to visual depictions of princely behavior, such as those in Rubens’s Medici cycle.43 Accetto defines dissimulation as the concealment or disguise of something, as opposed to simulation, which is the pretence of what is not, in affectation, fabrication, or counterfeiting.44 Thus defined, dissimulation unites aspects of crypsis (avoiding detection) and masquerade (preventing recognition). Indeed, sometimes a connection is made between human dissimulation and animal camouflage: Baltasar Gracián advises the courtier that “the most practical sort of knowledge lies in dissimulation…. Oppose lynxes of discourse with inky cuttlefish of interiority. Let no one discover your inclinations, no one foresee them, either to contradict or to flatter them.”45 Gracián’s counsel suggests that dissimulation in humans often connected to their indulging in their irrational, animal nature.47

Animal features figure prominently in one of the most detailed studies of human social camouflage and mimicry, the Mémoires of the duc de Saint-Simon (1675–1755). Published in the nineteenth century following the royal sequestration of the manuscript after the author’s death, the work gives a full and surpassingly vivid account of the last decade of the rule of Louis XIV and the Regency. It also stands out for its depiction of court life as a menagerie in which aristocrats strive to adapt their behavior to that of the royal family and new arrivals or social climbers attempt to camouflage traces of their lowly origins. This rendering of court life in terms of animal behavior is underpinned by Saint-Simon’s use of animal traits and metaphors to characterize the subjects of the written portraits that punctuate his narrative.

Thus, the courtier Henri Pussort has the face of an angry cat; the Villars couple are two-legged rats who flee the court of the dying king just as rats flee houses on the brink of collapse; Jeanne de Mouchy-Montcraval is a woodcock; the prince de Carignan, a circus animal; the marquis de Feuquières, a furious dog; the Abbé de Vaubrun, a vile and dangerous slug; the comte de Pontchartrain, a poisonous spider; the duc du Maine, one of the king’s bastard sons, a rattlesnake. The duc de Noailles is the perfect imitation of the snake who corrupted Paradise; the Prince de Condé believes himself to be a dog, whereas the servants of the duc de Vendôme behave like a pack of hunting dogs. The duchesse de Gesvre resembles a crane in her overall appearance and gait.48 Incidentally, cranes featured prominently in the zoo at Versailles and in representations of its animals in the sumptuous cycle of tapestries commemorating royal residences and the months of the year. Exotic animals in the foregrounds of those woven scenes often mimicked the behavior of courtiers, their gestures and bearing (fig. 13).

Fig. 13. Charles Le Brun (French, 1619–1690), June, Fontainebleau, from the tapestry series the Months, or the Royal Houses, 1670s, Manufacture des Gobelins, Paris. Wool, silk, and gold thread, 13 feet 9½ in. × 21 feet 3½ in. (4.2 × 6.5 m). Mobilier national, Paris (GMTT-108-006). Photo: Wikimedia commons.

Saint-Simon’s character sketch of the duc de Noailles merits close scrutiny because it shows clearly the author’s use of animal hypotyposis and metonymy to analyze camouflage behavior. “The serpent who tempted Eve, who overturned Adam through her, and who ruined the human species, is the original of which the duc de Noailles is the most exact, the most faithful, the most perfect copy…. A life spent in darkness, closeted, enemy of light, preoccupied by his ambitions … depth without substance…. Language of the courtier, jargon of women, convivial, without taste if necessary, dressed instantly according to the tastes of anybody he is with.”49

These few short sentences present a compelling portrait of social mimicry. The dissimulation of the duc de Noailles is not the behavior expected of a courtier who has read Castiglione on the ideal comportment of someone of his rank or Torquato Accetto’s essay on honest dissimulation. It is instead an integral part of what Saint-Simon considers to be the duke’s profoundly bestial nature. The effect that Saint-Simon’s description of the duke has on the reader, like the cumulative effect of all the other zoomorphisms in the portraits of the inhabitants of Versailles, creates profound uncertainty about the ontological status of the animal in the Mémoires as well as at the court. Is the author’s use of animal traits to evoke or, rather, figure the character of the courtiers simply a stylistic strategy? If that is so, why do these identifications work so well? Are these courtiers in fact poorly disguised animals and Saint-Simon is the one who rips off their human masks? Or are they humans who fail to master the animal parts of their nature? An affirmative response to this last question is supported by a passage in which Saint-Simon notes that when the duc de Beauvillier, bereft of his best friend, masters his grief, he completes the destruction of his inner animal nature.50

Saint-Simon was not unique in playing on readers’ uneasy awareness of the fragile border between animal and human nature. La Fontaine’s Fables exercised their hold on the popular imagination in part because of their ontological oscillations: it is never quite clear whether they portray humans disguised as animals or animals disguised as humans. Another major ingredient of this new figuration of animality was contributed by Charles Le Brun (1609–1690), first painter to Louis XIV. Le Brun’s studies of animal and human physiognomy culminated in renderings of unsettling faces that combine animal and human features and thus transcend the barriers between species (fig. 14).51When the studies were displayed at the Louvre in 1794, crowds flocked to the exhibition, making it the museum’s most popular attraction. The journalist and urbanist Sébastien Mercier gave a suggestive account of viewers’ reactions, reporting that they scrutinized Le Brun’s drawings and then started to search the faces of people around them for likenesses to animal faces. At the end of their visits, the spectators all slunk away to cast furtive glances in the mirrors hanging near the exit, where they checked to see whether they themselves looked like eagles or chickens, camels or lions, apes or swine. “It is an instinct,” Mercier wrote.52

Fig. 14. Charles Le Brun, pl. 32 from Louis-Marie-Joseph Morel d’Arleux, Dissertation sur un traité de Charles Le Brun concernant le rapport de la physionomie humaine avec celle des animaux (Paris: Chalcographie du Louvre, 1806). Photo: Wellcome Trust.

All the approximations of animal and human behavior and appearance cited above—particularly Saint-Simon’s animal figurations of human camouflage and mimicry—are instances of cultural practices or techniques in the sense outlined in the introduction to this article. They arise in a context of newly emerging social and scientific cultures; they are concerned with the construction and presentation of social identities; and they lend themselves to reflection and thematization. The anecdote by Mercier is particularly telling, as it presents both the first-order visual questioning of the relation between the animal and the human by Le Brun and the second-order thematization of that questioning in the reactions of those who attended the exhibition of his work.

2.3. Masking and the emergence of human culture

In the 1860s, at the time of Darwin’s and Wallace’s first theorizations of camouflage as a means of the survival of species, the architect and architectural theorist Gottfried Semper (1803–1879) developed a theory of the emergence of human material culture in which masking plays a central role. Semper was well aware of evolution theory but felt its analysis of the development of species was too general and on too large a timescale to be applied profitably to human culture. Yet what he said about dressing and masking as the defining characteristics of art and about their theatrical essence comes strikingly close to what Wallace said about the theatrical aspect of animal camouflage—that it can make animals appear as actors or masqueraders.

For Semper, all cultures originate in what he posited as the four primitive crafts: weaving, carpentry, masonry, and metalwork. Human societies emerge when a tribe gathers around a fire to tell stories about ancestors and marks off the space with woven grass, fiber, and, subsequently, textile. Thus, a space is created using a partition, pen, or fence made of plaited or interwoven sticks and branches. In a revolutionary move, Semper argues that the origin and essence of architecture are not construction but the visible representation of enclosed space. Architecture is thus intimately linked to weaving or textile, one of the four primitive crafts found all over the world and that form the cradle of human art and industry: “The beginning of building coincides with the beginning of textiles.”53 Inspired by the re-creation of a Trinidadian bamboo hut that he had seen in London at the Great Exhibition of 1851, Semper breaks with the classical tradition of considering the petite cabane rustique —that is, a building and its construction—as the origin of architecture. Instead, in a fundamental rethinking of an artistic tradition in anthropological terms, he located architecture’s origins in the craft of weaving, which made the action of space creation possible by providing woven curtains, carpets, and tents.54

According to Semper, the shift from ephemeral textile constructions to enduring stone structures was impelled by the human drive to create lasting, monumental records of important political and religious acts, situations, and rituals. With the change came dressing and masking: marble slabs, stucco, and polychromy mask and dress the interior structure of buildings. Architecture, Semper maintained, is not an art of construction but of masquerade and disguise, as are most human arts, including the theater. He famously observed that the torchlit masquerade of Carnival is the best atmosphere in which to enjoy art.55

Semper elaborated this hypothetical etiology into an anthropological theory that identifies the innate human urge to act and to mask reality as the origin of all art. (The anthropologist Gustav Klemm, Semper’s contempory, called this urge Darstellungstrieb —the instinctual urge to represent.56) He claimed, in other words, that the material origins of building can be traced to the craft of weaving but that the transformation of building into an art form was sparked by the human instinct to disguise, play, and represent—and thereby to appropriate and survive.57 An early Chinese vase now in the Museum Rietberg in Zürich and unfortunately not known to Semper presents a good example of the human urge to mask and disguise. Its textured surface bears the imprint of a woven fabric that was pressed against the vessel’s surface to leave a decorative pattern (fig. 15).

Fig. 15. Ewer with impressed textile pattern, Shang Dynasty, 1200–1100 BCE, Zhejiang region, China. Fired clay, height ca. 11¾ in. (30 cm). Museum Rietberg, Zurich. Photo: Caroline van Eck.

In Semper’s view, the production of masks to be worn on the face, head, or entire body was preceded by the practice of tattooing, which is closely related to cannibalism as a founding rite of human societies. Created by deliberate human action performed directly on the body, tattooing occupies an intriguing intermediate position between the external artifact of the mask and the bodily metamorphosis effected by animal camouflage. Semper argued that polychromy is an externalization of tattooing and that it constituted the first manifestation of the principle of dressing and masking, which for him characterizes all art.

Semper’s concept of masking is closer to masquerade, designed to avoid recognition, than to crypsis, employed to avoid detection. Walls dressed in stucco, marble, or tiles mask the original craft and materials—the masonry or carpentry—used to construct them. The anthropological driver of this transformation of craft into art goes back to humans’ early use of animal masks created through a gesture of appropriation. As I have written elsewhere, it could be argued by extension that animal camouflage and human image-making meet in the mask.58 The mask is a man-made artifact used by humans to hide their real appearance, look like another living being, frighten, terrify, or pass unnoticed—in short, to perform some of the same functions as camouflage, but with different mechanisms. In his magnum opus, Der Stil (1860–63), Semper connected the custom shared by early societies across the world of wearing animal skins and masks to chase away enemies and terrify believers into submission:

Thus even today the Prairie Indians hide their heads behind frightful animal masks during their savage war dances; masks taken from bisons or bears. One finds a similar mask ornamentation among the savages of the South Sea Islands. Such horrible animal masks appear among Egyptian priests in a more refined design as the hieratic head ornament of the priest who represents the god. Thus the animal mask became the early symbol for disguise, hiding, the secret, and the terrifying. Often nothing remained of this except the particularly characteristic features of the animal, as in the use of bull horns to ornament the Mitra of Assyrian rulers…. The terrifying Gorgon of Pallas Athena is a mask. It was long a most significant symbol in life as in the arts before the dramatic arts appropriated it; and here as well we see the apparently most refined product of antique art grafted on the earliest origins of nature. 59

In the next stages of the development of human art, monuments are erected to commemorate the religious, political, or cultural founding moments of a society. Semper describes this progression in what we would now call material culture as a process of Stoffwechsel (metamorphosis, or metabolism), in which motifs associated with the four primitive crafts migrate from one medium to another across time and space. His major example is weaving, which in many respects he considered to be the foundational human craft. It originated in Egypt, developing into fabrics, curtains, and tapestries used to cover walls. These began to be represented on painted tiles in Mesopotamia and subsequently migrated across time, place, and genres into ephemeral hangings used in triumphal processions and ceremonies. This process of Stoffwechsel reached a first culmination in stone representations of tapestries used in ephemeral triumphs that were carved on Roman triumphal arches.

Historians of the decorative arts such as Alois Riegl (1858–1905) demonstrated that many of Semper’s hypotheses about the historical details of cultural development were incorrect. Nevertheless, Semper’s theory of the emergence of human culture in the transition from primitive crafts to artistic practices such as tapestry-making and architecture is, in my view, one of the best and most fully documented studies of the advent of what we would now call a cultural technique. Weaving existed before it was conceptualized, it developed into a codified practice inextricably linked to its medium, and it is clearly capable of thematization. Semper’s concept of Stoffwechsel elucidates this process of emergence. His theory of dressing and masking and the theatrical nature of the visual arts—theatrical in that they are always meant to be seen—is a particularly telling analysis of how thematization in the visual arts and architecture can work.60 And not least, Semper offers an understanding of camouflage, here in the sense of masquerade, as a human cultural technique that originates in the appropriation of animal heads as masks to be used in the same way animals use facial coloring and expression to hide or to terrify.

Conclusion

Despite the evident and often striking similarities between animal camouflage or mimicry and human image-making, understanding this relation is not easy because of the complexities that appear once those similarities are questioned. These complexities include how to relate the respective evolutionary developments of animal camouflage and human image-making and how to relate the visual and intellectual competences implied by camouflage that enable both animals and humans, as Caillois suggested, to see circles as eyes and in general to see something as something else—the phenomenon known as “seeing in/ seeing as,” or aspectual seeing.61Considering human behavior or image-making in terms of camouflage and mimicry raises complex issues about intentionality and the degree to which such behavior, even though it looks very similar to animal appearance and behavior, is in fact related to it. Before we start to define this relation, a corpus of cases of human camouflage and mimicry needs to be established; and to establish that corpus or catalogue, criteria for inclusion and categories to guide the search for cases have to be defined. Defining human camouflage and mimicry as cultural technique is a first step that offers a way of thinking about the relation between nature and culture. The three contexts outlined here for such human behavior and image-making are pointers that can guide further searches.

Notes

Caroline van Eck is professor of art history at the University of Cambridge and the author of Piranesi’s Candelabra and the Presence of the Past: Excessive Objects and the Emergence of a Style in the Age of Neoclassicism (Oxford University Press, 2023).

I am much indebted to the suggestions of two anonymous readers of this article. I greatly benefited from conversations at seminars of the Cambridge-Ghent Network for Camouflage with Maude Bass-Krueger, Lorenzo Bartalesi, Caroline Humphrey, Stijn Bussels, Philippe Descola, Pascal Griener, Odile Nouvel, and Bram Van Oostveldt. I am even more indebted to Hende Bauer for her deep knowledge and endless patience in answering my questions about evolution theory.

  1. 1  See Ulrich Pfisterer, “Animal Art/Human Art: Imagined Borderlines in the Renaissance,” in Human Minds: The Renaissance and Its Anthropologies, ed. Andreas Höfele and S. Laqué (Berlin: De Gruyter 2011), 224–27. On depictions of monkeys as painters see Horst Janson, Apes and Ape Lore in the Middle Ages and the Renaissance (London: Warburg Institute, 1952); Ingrid Roscoe, “Mimic without Mind: Singerie in Northern Europe,” Apollo: The International Magazine of Arts 114, no. 234 (1981): 96–103; Sarah Cohen, Enlightened Animals in Eighteenth-Century Art, Sensation, Matter, and Knowledge (Bloomsbury Publishing, 2021); Mary Sheriff, “Reflecting on Chardin,” The Eighteenth Century: Theory and Interpretation 29, no. 1 (1988): 19–45, 37.,
  2. 2 Erwin Panofsky, Tomb Sculpture (New York: Pantheon Books, 1964), 26–37. Intriguingly, this phenomenon was defined in exactly the same terms and at roughly the same time by Claude Lévi-Strauss in his discussion of the similarities between Northwest Coast art and the art of ancient China. See Claude Lévi-Strauss, Structural Anthropology (New York: Basic Books, 1963), 246; and Yves-Alain Bois, “On the Uses and Abuses of Look-Alikes,” October 154 (2015): 127–49. These authors discuss such similarities as they appear in artworks and artifacts across periods and cultures but not across animal and human image-making. Gyorgy Kepes, the Hungarian-born painter, theorist, and educator who taught at the New Bauhaus and MIT and was involved in military camouflage design during World War II, did study pseudomorphosis across human artifacts and natural forms in the exhibition “The New Landscape” (MIT, 1951) and the book The New Landscape in Art and Science (Chicago: Paul Theobald, 1956). For an exploration of pseudomorphosis in twentieth-century design, see John R. Blakinger, Gyorgy Kepes: Undreaming the Bauhaus (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2019), 103, 105, and 128; for relations between Kepes’s work, Warburg’s Mnemosyne Atlas, and Malraux’s Musée Imaginaire, see Spyros Papapetros, On the Animation of the Inorganic: Art, Architecture, and the Extension of Life (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2012), 150.
  3. 3 On the military history of camouflage see Roy Behrens, False Colours: Art, Design and Modern Camouflage (Dysart, IA: Bobolink Books, 2002); Roy Behrens, Camoupedia: A Compendium of Research on Art, Architecture, and Camouflage (Dysart, IA: Bobolink Books, 2009); Roy Behrens, “Nature’s Artistry: Abbott H. Thayer’s Assertions about Camouflage in Art, War and Nature,” in Animal Camouflage, ed. M. Stevens and S. Merilaita (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011), 87–100. On Abbott Thayer, one of the main designers and theorists of animal camouflage and its military uses, see Kevin Murphy, Not Theories but Revelations: The Art and Science of Abbott Handerson Thayer (exh. cat. Williams College Museum of Art, 2016), and Maggie Cao, “Abbott Thayer and the Invention of Camouflage,” Art History, 39, no. 3 (2016): 486–511. For the French role in the development of military camouflage see Cécile Coutin, Tromper l’ennemi: L’invention du camouflage moderne en 1914–1918 (Paris: Editions Pierre de Taillac, 2012); for recent developments in military camouflage and its cultural ramifications see, for instance, Ann Elias, Camouflage Australia: Art, Nature, Science and War (Sydney: Sydney University Press, 2011); David L. Williams, Dazzle, Disruption and Concealment: The Science, Psychology and Art of Ship Camouflage (Cheltenham: History Press, 2022); and Michael Taussig, “Zoology, Magic, and Surrealism in the War on Terror,” Critical Inquiry 34 (2007): 98–116.
  4. 4 Thomas Macho, “Second-Order Animals: Cultural Techniques of Identity and Identification,” Theory, Culture and Society 30, no. 6 (2013): 30–47. In the same volume, see also the overview of theories of cultural techniques by Geoffrey Winthrop-Young, “Cultural Techniques: Preliminary Remarks,” 3–19.
  5. 5 This problematical aspect of using evolution theory to understand cultural development was pointed out in the nineteenth century by Gottfried Semper. See Sonja Hildebrand, “Concepts of Creation: Historiography and Design in Gottfried Semper,” Journal of Art Historiography 11 (2004): 1–11. On levels of resolution in cultural analysis see David Wengrow, The Origins of Monsters: Image and Cognition in the First Age of Mechanical Reproduction (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2015), 3–7.
  6. 6 The best historical overview of camouflage and mimicry is by Peter Forbes, Dazzled and Deceived: Mimicry and Camouflage (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2011). See also Hanna Shell, Hide and Seek: Camouflage, Photography, and the Media of Reconnaissance (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012).
  7. 7 Le Grand Robert de la langue française, ed. Alain Rey and Danièle Morvan (Paris: Editions Robert, 2001), s.v. camouflage.
  8. 8 Mary Alice Evans, “Mimicry and the Darwinian Heritage,” Journal of the History of Ideas 26 (1965): 211–20; see, for instance, Charles Darwin, On the Origin of Species (London: J. Murray, 1859), 72–73.
  9. 9 William Kirby and William Spence, Introduction to Entomology, or, Elements of the Natural History of Insects (London: Longman, 1815), vol. 1, 9.
  10. 10 Kirby and Spence, Introduction to Entomology (London: Longman, 1818), vol. 2, 223.
  11. 11 For a recent analysis of mimicry and its varieties, see Gabriel M. Jamie, “Signals, Cues and the Nature of Mimicry,” Proceedings of the Royal Society B 284 (2017), https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2016.2080; see also Martin Stevens and Sami Merilaita, introduction to special issue on camouflage, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 364 (2008): 423–24, https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2008.0217; William Kimler and Michael Ruse, “Mimicry and Camouflage,” in The Cambridge Encyclopedia to Darwin and Evolutionary Thought, ed. Michael Ruse (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), 139–45, and in the same volume Joseph Travis, “Mimicry and Camouflage: Part Two,” 336–39. See also, for the history of thought about mimicry before Darwin, Michel Boulard, “Mimétisme,” in Dictionnaire du Darwinisme et de l’évolution, ed. Patrick Tort (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1996), with bibliography.
  12. 12 Muriel Blaisdell, “Natural Theology and Nature’s Designs,” Journal of the History of Biology 15 (1982): 163–89, https://doi.org/10.1007/bf00233013. For the impact of Darwin’s ideas on the arts, see Endless Forms. Charles Darwin, Natural Science and the Visual Arts, ed. Diana Arnold and Jane Munro (Cambridge: Fitzwilliam Museum/New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2009).
  13. 13 Henry W. Bates, “Contributions to an Insect Fauna of the Amazon Valley, Lepidoptera: Heliconidae,” Transactions of the Linnaean Society London 23 (1862): 495–566; see also his widely read The Naturalist on the River Amazons: A Record of Adventures, Habits of Animals, Sketches of Brazilian and Indian Life, and Aspects of Nature under the Equator During Eleven Years of Travel (London: J. Murray, 1863); and Charles Darwin, “[Review of] Contributions to an Insect Fauna of the Amazon Valley. By Henry Walter Bates [ … ],” Natural History Review 3 (1863): 219–24. See also William C. K imler, One Hundred Years of Mimicry: History of an Evolutionary Exemplar (PhD diss., Cornell University, 1983), which traces the development from Christian natural theology to Darwin’s evolution theory.
  14. 14 See Kimler and Ruse, “Mimicry and Camouflage,” 140.
  15. 15 Alfred Wallace, “Mimicry, and Other Protective Resemblances among Animals,” Westminster and Foreign Quarterly Review ( July 1867): 9.
  16. 16 Hugh Cott, Adaptive Coloration in Animals (London: Methuen 1940), 438. On the Cambridge debate see William Kimler, “Mimicry: Views of Naturalists and Ecologists before the Modern Synthesis,” in Dimensions of Darwinism: Themes and Counterthemes in Twentieth-Century Evolutionary Theory, ed. Margaret Grene (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983), 97–128; and Victoria N. Alexander, “Chance, Nature’s Practical Jokes, and the ‘Non-Utilitarian Delights’ of Butterfly Mimicry,” in Fine Lines: Vladimir Nabokov’s Scientific Art, ed. Stephen H. Blackwell and Kurt Johnson (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2016), 225–35.
  17. 17 Wallace, “Mimicry,” 40.
  18. 18 Wallace, 42.
  19. 19 Richard Swann Lull, Organic Evolution (New York: MacMillan, 1917), 246, quoted in Forbes, Dazzled and Deceived, 47.
  20. 20 Forbes, 197–207.
  21. 21 Alexander, “Chance, Nature’s Practical Jokes, and the ‘Non-Utilitarian Delights’ of Butterfly Mimicry.”
  22. 22 Brian Boyd and R. M. Pyle, eds., Nabokov’s Butterflies: Unpublished and Uncollected Writings (Boston: Beacon, 2000), 224–27.
  23. 23 Boyd and Pyle, 178.
  24. 24 Victoria Alexander, “Nabokov, Teleology and Insect Mimicry,” Nabokov Studies 7 (2002/2003): 177–213, https://doi.org/10.1353/nab.2010.0004.
  25. 25 Roger Caillois, “La mante religieuse: De la biologie à la psychanalyse,” in Minotaure 5 (1934), and Roger Caillois, The Mask of Medusa, trans. George Ordish (New York: Clarkson N. Potter, 1964). The latter was originally published in French as Méduse et Cie (Paris: Gallimard, 1960).
  26. 26 Roger Caillois, Le mimétisme animal (Paris: Hachette, 1963), 49: “Le camouflage est souvent inutile …. Il y a luxe de précaution, excès de simulacre.” Translations are by the author unless otherwise indicated.
  27. 27 “La connection du mimétisme et des ocelles ne saurait être due au hasard. Il y a entre les deux phénomènes un lien qu’il convient de déceler. Je l’aperçois pour ma part dans le mécanisme de l’exhibition des ocelles fascinateurs. Il ne suffit pas qu’ils existent, il faut qu’ils apparaissent. D’abord invisibles, ils éclatent tout d’un coup. Le camouflage … le confond avec le milieu, il empêche qu’on l’en distingue. Alors soudain, là où il semblait n’y a voir rien, d’une sorte d’absence ou au moins de présence neutre, difficile à repérer, douteuse, surgissent des cercles énormes aux couleurs vives, invraisemblables, dont la fixité fascine…. L’insecte opère à la façon d’un masque à volets: à une apparance, il en substitue une autre, qui effraie. Mieux: à la place du néant, c’est soudain le visage de l’épouvante.” Ibid.
  28. 28 For a more extensive discussion of Caillois, see Caroline van Eck, “Camouflage, Zoomorphism, and the Origins of Image-Making,” in Image, Thought, and the Making of Social Worlds: Freiburger Studien zur Archäologie und Visuellen Kultur, ed. David Wengrow (Heidelberg: Propylaeum, 2022), 91–114, https://doi.org/10.11588/propylaeum.842.c10807.
  29. 29 For a summary of these critiques, see Forbes, Dazzled and Deceived, 127–37.
  30. 30 Stevens and Merilaita, 423–24 and 431. For a synthesis of recent research into animal physiology of perception see Ed Yong, An Immense World: How Animal Senses Reveal the World around Us (New York: Random House, 2022).
  31. 31 Friedrich Nietzsche, “Vom Nutzen und Nachtheil der Geschichte für das Leben,” in Samtliche Werke: Kritische Studienausgabe in 15 Bänden, ed. Giorgio Colli and Mazzino Montinari (Berlin/New York: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag/de Gruyter, 1980), vol. 1, 333. I am much indebted here to Kyung-Ho Cha, Humanmimikry: Poetik der Evolution (Munich: Wilhelm Fink, 2010), 125–66. A book by Gottfried Semper’s nephew Karl Semper, Die natürlichen Existenzbedingungen der Thiere (Leipzig: Brockhouse, 1880), offers a summary of Fritz Müller’s theory of mimicry, which was the major foundation for Nietzsche’s ideas in this context. On Nietzsche and Darwin see John Richardson, Nietzsche’s New Darwinism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004). For Nietzsche’s deduction of human acting from animal mimicry, see Fröhliche Wissenschaft, Kritische Studienausgabe vol. I, 608. See also Kritische Studienausgabe vol. IX, 173: “Die Thiere welche durch eine entsetzliche Buntheit aller Augen auf sich ziehen, werden trotzdem sehr in Ruhe gelassen: sie haben alle eine böse Waffe, ein Gift und dergleichen— Gleichniß,” [“The animals that through a terrifying variety of color attract all eyes are nevertheless very much left in peace: they all have an evil weapon, a poison and so on—similarity”], and Kritische Studienausgabe vol. XI, 111.
  32. 32 Friedrich Nietzsche, Kritische Studienausgabe, vol. I, 36–37, § 26: “Die Thiere und die Moral.—Die Praktiken, welche in der verfeinerten Gesellschaft gefordert werden: das sorgfältige Vermeiden des … Auffälligen, . . heftigeren Begehrungen … —dies Alles als die gesellschaftliche Moral ist im Groben überall bis in die tiefste Thierwelt hinab zu finden—und erst in dieser Tiefe sehen wir die Hinterabsicht aller dieser liebenswürdigen Vorkehrungen: man will seinen Verfolgern entgehen und im Aufsuchen seiner Beute glücklich sein. Desshalb lernen die Thiere sich beherrschen und sich in der Weise verstellen, dass manche zum Beispiel ihre Farben der Farbe der Umgebung anpassen … oder die Formen und Farben eines andern Thieres oder von Sand, Blättern, Flechten, Schwammen annehmen…. Zu allen den feinen Arten, uns glücklich mächtig, verliebt zu stellen, wird man leicht das thierische Gleichniss finden…. Das Thier beurtheilt die Bewegungen seiner Gegner und Freunde, es lernt ihre Eigenthümlichkeiten auswendig, es richtet sich auf diese ein.” English translation in Friedrich Nietzsche, Daybreak: Thoughts on the Prejudices of Morality, ed. Maudemarie Clark and Brian Leiter (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 20–21.
  33. 33 See, for instance, Martha C. Nussbaum’s overview of recent studies on the porous boundaries between animal and human behavior, in which the author takes the view that any animal capable of deception is capable of metacognition. Martha C. Nussbaum, “What We Owe Our Fellow Animals,” New York Review of Books, March 10, 2022; and Mark S. Blumberg, “Development Evolving: The Science and Meanings of Instinct,” Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science 8 (2017): 1–7.
  34. 34 Frans de Waal, Are We Smart Enough to Know How Smart Animals Are? (New York: Norton, 2016), for instance, 94; Tetsuro Matsuzawa, “Kinji Imanishi and 60 Years of Japanese Primatology,” Current Biology 18 (2008): 587–91, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2008.05.040.
  35. 35 See Chantal Conneller, “Becoming Deer: Corporeal Transformations at Star Carr,” Archaeological Dialogues 11 (2004): 37–56.
  36. 36 Homer, Odyssey, 9:413–63.
  37. 37Historia Animalium, 9:622a 2–10.
  38. 38 See Der Neue Pauly, ed. Hubert Cancik and Helmuth Schneider (Stuttgart: J. B. Metzler, 2000), s.v. Oppianus.
  39. 39 Oppianus, Treatise on Fishing, 2:232–33, in A. W. Mair, Oppian, Colluthus, Tryphiodorus, trans. A. W. Mair (London: Loeb Classical Library 1928), 304. Quoted in Marcel Detienne and Jean-Pierre Vernant, Les ruses de l’intelligence: La mètis des Grecs (Paris: Flammarion, 1974), 44–48.
  40. 40 Detienne and Vernant, Les ruses de l’intelligence, 50.
  41. 41 The caption to print no. 32 in the Philips Galle edition: Sic bove fictitio contecti, sulphuris ictu/Accensi occidunt pavidos formidine Cervos, quoted in Welmoet Bok-van Kammen, Stradanus and the Hunt (PhD diss., Johns Hopkins University, 1977), 336; caption to print no. 12 in the Galle edition, quoted in Katrin Achilles, Johannes Stradanus: Venationes Avium. Zur Darstellung der Vogeljagd in der Graphik des 16. Jahrhunderts (MA thesis, TU Berlin, 1980), vol. 1, 113–16: Veste bovis operit, clam sturnos fallit edaces/Venator, pisitat dum garrula ab ilice perdrix. The use of such camouflage devices was described in antiquity, as Katrin Achilles points out: see Dionysios, Ixeutikon seu de aucupio libri tres, ed. A. Garzya (Leipzig: Teubner, 1963) III.7, 41; and was described in the Middle Ages by Gaston Phébus in his Livre de Chasse (1387–89), sec. LXXVI.
  42. 42 Jacobus Bornitius, Emblematum ethico-politicorum sylloge (Heidelberg: Ludwig Bourgeat, 1664): “Cui fidas, videas: tanta est dissimulatio secli!/Si quis ait, negat is: sin negat, ipsius ait.”
  43. 43 Torquato Accetto, Della dissimulazione onesta (Naples 1641) § xi; modern editions in Politici e Moralisti del Seicento, ed. Benedetto Croce (Bari: Laterza: 1930), and in Torquato Accetto, Della dissimulazione onesta, ed. Salvatore Silvano Nigro (Turin: Einaudi, 1997), here 63. On such dissimulation see Jean-Pierre Cavaillé, Dis/simulations. Jules-César Vanini, François La Mothe Le Vayer, Gabriel Naudé, Louis Machon et Torquato Accetto. Religion, morale et politique au XVIIe siècle (Paris: Champion, 2002); Horst Bredekamp et al., eds., Dissimulazione Onesta oder Die ehrliche Verstellung: Von der Weisheit der Versteckten Beunruhigung in Wort, Bild und Tat (Hamburg: Philo & Philo Fine Arts, 2007), and Jon Snyder, Dissimulation and the Culture of Secrecy in Early Modern Europe (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2009) have overviews of early modern thought on dissimulation; for its role in the Medici Cycle see Sara Galletti, “Rubens’s Life of Maria de’ Medici: Dissimulation and the Politics of Art in Early Seventeenth-Century France,” Renaissance Quarterly 67, no. 3 (2014): 878–916.
  44. 44 Torquato Accetto, Della dissimulazione onesta, ed. Nigro, 27.
  45. 45  Baltasar Gracián, Art of Worldly Wisdom, 54–55 (aphorism 98), quoted in Jon Snyder, Dissimulation and the Culture of Secrecy, 46.
  46. 46 Torquato Accetto, Della dissimulazione onesta, § xi.[/note But something changes in France in the 1660s: human behavior, and in particular human courtly behavior, is still often analyzed in terms of dissimulation, but animal associations increasingly dominate the analysis and underlying imaginative framework as well as the verbal and visual representation of such behavior.

    2.2. Animality and social camouflage at the French court

    While animal symbolism had always been in use at the French court, a change in the perception of the relation between animals and humans took hold and evolved there in the 1660s. Peter Sahlins, in his recent study 1668: The Year of the Animal, shows the court moving away from the radical Cartesian distinction between brute beasts and soul-possessing humans and toward an awareness of the porous nature of this separation. The new attitude manifested itself in many aspects of science and culture. At Versailles, Louis XIV installed a new menagerie and a labyrinth full of animal personifications of human character traits, in the form of statues and topiary; a public debate arose about the sentient nature and sociability of chameleons; and early defenses of animal intelligence included an argument by the king’s physician, Marin Cureau de la Chambre, in the fourth book of his Traité des Passsions (1642), that animal behavior shows evidence of intelligence, memory, judgment, and emotions. 4647 Peter Sahlins, 1668: The Year of the Animal in France (New York: Zone Books, 2017), in particular 91–123 on the royal menagerie, 277–311 on the chameleon debate, and 191–244 on Charles Le Brun and Cureau de la Chambre.

  47. 48 Saint-Simon, Mémoires, ed. Yves Coirault (Paris: Bibliothèque de la Pléiade, 1983–1988): 1:356; 1:607; 3:255 and 3:126, n9; 3:466; 3:427; 2:1153–54; 4:863; 6:37 and 6:409; see also the article by Frédéric Charbonneau, “Le Bestiaire de Saint-Simon,” in Les Songes de Clio: Fiction et Histoire sous l’Ancien Régime, ed. Sabrina Vervacke et al. (Laval: Les Presses de l’Université de Laval, 2006), 157–71; Dirk Van der Cruysse, Le Portrait dans les Mémoires de Saint-Simon (Paris: Nizet, 1971); and Nadir Weber, “Das Bestiarium du Duc de Saint-Simon,” Zeitschrift für historische Forschung 43 (2016): 27–59.
  48. 49 Saint-Simon, Mémoires, 5:283ff: “Le serpent qui tenta Eve, qui renversa Adam par elle, et qui perdit le genre humain, est l’original dont le duc de Noailles est la copie la plus exacte, la plus fidèle, la plus parfaite…. Une vie ténébreuse, enfermée, ennemie de la lumière, toute occupée de projets … une profondeur sans fond…. Language de courtisan, jargon des femmes, bon convive, sans aucun goût quand il le faut, revêtu sur-le-champ des goûts de chacun.”
  49. 50 Saint-Simon, Mémoires, 4:863: “La mort du duc de Chevreuse combla en lui la déstruction de l’homme animal.” See Marcus Wild, Der anthropologische Differenz: Der Geist der Tiere bei Montaigne, Descartes, Hume (Berlin: Degruyter, 2006), 17–31.
  50. 51 On Le Brun’s hybrid faces, see also Sarah Cohen, “Searching the Animal Psyche with Charles Le Brun,” Annals of Science 67 (2010): 353–82.
  51. 52 Louis-Sébastien Mercier: Le Nouveau Paris, ed. Jean-Claude Bonnet (Paris: Mercure de France, 1994), 788–89. See also Anne Richardot, “La ménagerie de Diderot (à propos du Neveu de Rameau),” Recherches sur Diderot et l’Encyclopédie 51 (2016): 3–17, https://doi.org/10.4000/rde.5377.
  52. 53 Gottfried Semper, Der Stil in den technischen und tektonischen Künsten, oder praktische Ästhetik: Ein Handbuch für Techniker, Künstler und Kunstfreunde (Frankfurt am Main: Kunst und Wissenschaft, 1860–63), vol. 1, 227.
  53. 54 Semper, Der Stil , vol. 2, 276, and reprinted in Kleine Schriften, ed. Hans and Manfred Semper (Berlin: Spemann, 1884), 383–93. In the latter volume, see also “Über architektonische Symbole” (1854), 292–303.
  54. 55 Semper, Der Stil, vol. 1, § 60, 323.
  55. 56 Gustav Klemm, Allgemeine Kulturwissenschaft. Die materiellen Grundlagen menschlichen Culturs. Einleitung. Das Feuer, die Nahrung, Getränke, Narkotika (Leipzig: Teubner, 1855), 55: “Die Darstellung der Erfahrung führt den Menschen zur Kunst…. Die Darstellung von Ereignissen mit Hilfe von Musik und Tanz rief schon bei den Jägerstämmen Amerikas das Drama ins Leben.” In his Allgemeine Kulturgeschichte der Menschheit (Leipzig: Teubner, 1843–51), vol. 1, 214, Klemm uses the term Darstellungstrieb.
  56. 57 See M. Hvattum, Gottfried Semper and the Problem of Historicism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 43. The idea of a theatrical essence of human nature and society was widespread in the 1860s. Charles Garnier, for instance, observed in the introduction to his book on the theater that “all that happens in the world is, in essence, only theatre and representation.” See Harry Mallgrave, Gottfried Semper: Architect of the Nineteenth Century (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1992), 345. For more detailed discussion of these points, see also Caroline van Eck, “Le cannibalisme, le tatouage, et le revêtement: de l’histoire de l’architecture à l’anthropologie de l’art,” Gradhiva: Revue d’anthropologie et des arts, special issue, Summer 2017: Gottfried Semper—habiter les couleurs, vol. 25 (2017), 24–49, and Van Eck, “The Primal Scene of Architecture: Gottfried Semper and Alfred Gell on the Origins of Art, Style and Agency,” Revue Germanique Internationale 26 (2017), https://doi.org/10.4000/rgi.1695.
  57. 58 Van Eck, “The Primal Scene of Architecture,” https://doi.org/10.4000/rgi.1695.
  58. 59 Semper, Der Stil vol. 1, § 27, 101. “So verstecken die Indianer der Prairie bei ihren wilden Kriegestänzen noch jetzt ihr Haupt hinter fürchterlichen Thiermasken, dem Bison oder dem Bären entnommen. Aehnlichen Maskenschmuck findet man bei den Wilden der Südseeinseln. Diese scheusslichen Thiermasken treten bei den ägyptischen Priestern in feinerer Ausbildung als hieratischer Kopfputz des den Gott repräsentirenden Priesters auf. Es wurde die Thiermaske das frühe Symbol der Verhüllung, des Geheimnissvollen, des Schreckbaren. Oft blieb davon nichts als das besonders charakteristische Abzeichen des Thieres übrig; z. B. die Stierhörner als Schmuck der Mitra der assyrischen Herrscher…. Das furchtbare Gorgeion der die Aegis schüttelnden Pallas Athene ist eine Maske. Diese war schon lange in dem Leben und in den Künsten ein bedeutsamstes Symbol, bevor die dramatische Kunst sich desselben bemächtigte; auch hier sehen wir wieder das scheinbar Raffinirteste der antiken Kunst unmittelbar auf die ursprünglichste Natur geimpft.”
  59. 60 Semper’s analysis of the emergence of human culture from plaiting and weaving is very close to Winthrop-Young’s discussion of the role of creating spaces by means of pens and doors in the emergence of cultural techniques. See Geoffrey Winthrop-Young, “Preliminary Remarks,” Theory, Culture and Society 30, no. 6 (2013): 11, https://doi.org/10.1177/0263276413500828.
  60. 61 See Richard Wollheim in Painting as an Art (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1992), 46–75; and Wollheim, “On Pictorial Representation,” in Richard Wollheim on the Art of Painting, ed. Rob van Gerwen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 13–28.

© 2020 Bard Graduate Center: Decorative Arts, Design History, Material Culture
West 86th is a publication of the Bard Graduate Center and the University of Chicago Press